Talking about present time
English uses a number of strategies to apply aspect to present
time. The form we use depends on the aspect we
perceive.
You may be mildly surprised to find the present perfect, the
going to formulation and the use of be + -ing
in this section. The argument is that, while they do refer to
future or past states or events, they do so premised on present states or
events and can only be understood with reference to the present.
In this sense they are relational not
absolute forms and belong here.
If you are expecting to find consideration of the present simple tense in English in this guide, you will be disappointed. That tense is considered in the guide to talking about always because it is a factual, absolute tense, unmarked for time.
Perfect aspect in the present |
|
It has rained It has been raining |
The clue to a major use of the present perfect lies in its name:
it is the present perfect.
If we want to refer to a present state of affairs or action
in relation to the past, this form will do it
for us.
For example:
The meaning I want to convey | Form of choice | Aspect |
I want to say that a current event is also a previous event | It has
rained all day and is still raining |
perfect |
I want to say that a change to the present event is the result of a recent finished past event | He has
finally arrived so now we can get on |
|
I want to say that a present state is the result of past event (recent or not) | I have
learned French. so now I can speak it |
|
I want to say that a present state is a continuation of a past state | I have
owned the house for some time and still do |
We can combine the perfect aspect with a continuous, progressive,
iterative, habitual, durative or prospective aspect and for these
purposes, we choose a different form. All the following retain the sense of the perfect
aspect, i.e., the relation of the present to the past but have an
additional aspect grafted on to them.
For example:
The meaning I want to convey | Form of choice | Aspect |
I want to say that a current state is also a previous state | I have been
feeling rough for a while and I still feel rough |
continuous |
I want to say that a current ongoing action is a continuation of a previous ongoing action | I have been walking quickly for
hours and am still walking quickly |
progressive |
I want to say that a current series of events is the continuation of a previous series of events | It has
been raining on and off all day. and is still raining on and off |
iterative |
I want to say that a routine continues from a previous routine | I have
been taking the 4 o'clock bus for years and it is still my habit to do this |
habitual |
I want to say that a current long-lasting action continues from a long-lasting action | I have
been thinking about it for a while. and continue to do so |
durative |
I want to say that a future event or state arises from a past event or state | I have
been meaning to talk to you for a while and will do so very soon The river has been rising all night and will soon flood the streets |
prospective |
Speakers will often choose prepositional phrases
(circumstances, if you prefer) to reinforce the meaning of what they
say from their point of view.
There is a guide to the present
perfect on this site but it does not focus on more than two
aspects.
One important point about the present perfect is that it can
refer to an imperfective or perfective use of the verb.
For example:
I have returned
is perfective, insofar as the returning is complete. Another
way to say this is that the verb use is telic, with a perceived end
point.
I have worked here for ten years
is imperfective because the implication is that I will go on working
here. Another way to say that is that the verb use is atelic,
having not end point in sight.
Progressive aspect in the present |
|
While he is walking in the
mountains, he looks out for bears |
The progressive aspect is not the same as the continuous. We can assert that something is ongoing, i.e., in progress, in three ways:
The meaning I want to convey | Form of choice | Aspect |
I want to say that an action is currently in progress | She is sitting on the bus,
reading War and Peace and loves the story right now |
progressive (all three) |
I want to say that an action is in progress but is not currently happening | She's reading War and Peace but may be at work now |
progressive |
I want to comment on or describe an action in progress | See, I open it like this, take
out the screws and put them aside Peterson moves quickly and scores |
Simple forms, with certain types of verbal processes, especially
mental processes such as enjoy, appreciate, love, understand
and verbal processes such as say, aver, assert, describe,
are often progressive in aspect but the tense choice is simple.
This is the effect of stative and dynamic use and is not
paralleled in many languages. Examples include:
She appreciates your hospitality
I understand the main points you are making
John says the weather will be better tomorrow
I describe it as deeply foolish
In all these cases, incidentally, the simple form of the verb is
used although the verb is atelic, have no explicitly stated end
point. This is slightly unusual because telicity is routinely
signalled by aspect in English with, e.g.:
I am living in London
which is atelic with no stated end point.
The unusual factor is that in the present tense, we can also express
an unfinished (atelic) event with the simple aspect:
I live in London.
This is not possible in the past because:
I was living in London
is atelic with no end point but:
I lived in London
implies the event is concluded and is a telic use.
Continuous aspect in the present |
|
I don't understand it I am not following you |
As with the progressive aspect, the continuous is expressed
through both the simple and more complex verb forms.
For example:
The meaning I want to convey | Form of choice | Aspect |
I want to say that a state currently exists | I feel terrible right now |
continuous |
I'm feeling better right now |
||
I want to say that a state of mind currently exists | I think that's astonishing but this cannot be a permanent condition |
|
I'm looking forward to meeting
you but this cannot be a permanent condition |
Here, too, the distinction between stative and dynamic verb
use is apparent but in some circumstances,
for example with the verb feel, they are interchangeable with little or no
change in meaning. When feel is used in the sense of
believe, it is timeless, usually, so we can have:
I feel that's mistaken
but not:
*I am feeling that's mistaken.
(For more on verbs encoding mental or verbal processes which are
used in the simple form when they are statements of timeless fact
and in the progressive form when they refer to ongoing mental
processes, see the guide to talking about
always. In that guide the short list of examples is:
believe, suggest, say, propose, aver, opine, avow, state, claim,
declare, swear, profess and so on.)
In all these cases, the verb is imperfective or atelic because no end point is explicit.
Durative aspect in the present |
|
I'm smoking too much |
English happens to distinguish between the habitual (which is not
solely a present aspect) and the durative.
For example:
The meaning I want to convey | Form of choice | Aspect |
I want to say that an action is a present long-standing routine which may cease | I'm staying at the Astor right now and for some time in the past and future |
durative |
I want to say that a long-standing state currently exists but may cease soon | It's cooling down a bit right now |
|
I want to say that a current event is understandable from previous experience of the same event | That'll be the neighbour's son
coming home That'll be the post arriving right now |
All of these could be described as progressive but the first
speaker may not be in the hotel now (so it isn't an action in
progress) and the second speaker may not be talking of weather at
this moment in time (so the state is not current). In both
cases, however, the event is unfinished.
A sub category of the durative, for which some languages have a
separate form, is the continuative which is signalled in English by
an adverbial of some kind rather than a tense form. For
example:
She is still eating.
Iterative aspect in the present |
|
Who's banging the drum? |
Note the distinction here with verb meaning:
Who's banging the drum?
is iterative (i.e., repeated) because the verb implies a short,
sharp action but
Who's playing the bagpipes?
is durative because the verb implies a long action.
The distinction between durative and iterative aspects in English
often lies in the meaning of the verb rather than the tense form.
That is not the case in other languages which may signal the uses in
distinct verb forms.
For example:
The meaning I want to convey | Form of choice | Aspect |
I want to say that an action may not be happening exactly at the moment of speaking but is happening now to all intents and purposes | Someone's knocking on the door right now but the knocks may be quite infrequent |
iterative |
I want to say that an action is repeated but may not be happening right now | People are forgetting to return
their books over a period of time, repeatedly |
Who bangs the drum? and Who plays the bagpipes? are iterative, not present per se.
Prospective aspect in the present |
|
Who's going to drive? Who's driving tomorrow? |
You may be slightly surprised to find what are often contrasted
as two future forms in the section on talking about the present.
However, seen from an understanding of prospective aspect, it makes
good sense.
Just as the perfect aspect (above) highlights the nature of a
present state of affairs or action in relation to the past, so the
prospective aspect highlights the relationship between a
current situation and the future.
Both the obviously present forms that we use to talk about the
future in that analysis are better understood as being rooted firmly
in the present.
The meaning I want to convey | Form of choice | Aspect |
I want to say that an action now will have a future fulfilment | So, we agree; I'm driving
tomorrow the agreement is current, the consequence is not |
prospective |
I want to say that a decision taken now will have a future fulfilment | I want to be clear:
I'm not going to drive the decision is now |
|
I want to say that a current state has future consequences | By the
look of those skies, it's going to rain again. the appearance of the sky is immediate and present |
|
I'm feeling a bit ill so I'm
taking tomorrow off the feeling is current and there's no obvious arrangement, incidentally |
The traditional analysis of these two forms as future indicators
is not without merit but their use for the future can only be
understood from previous events or states.
The distinction between an intention with going to and an
arrangement (with the -ing form), if it is sustainable at
all, can only be discovered by reference to actions or states at a
time before the future.
It is sometimes said, with reason, that when discussing plans and
arrangements (for which we use the present progressive form) or
intentions (for which we use the going to structure) the
forms are, in fact much more fluid than the simple dichotomy
suggests. Functionally, there is little distinction between
the meanings of the forms, so:
He's taking a holiday next week
carries the same meaning as
He's going to take a holiday next week
and
I'm going to see my mother on Monday
and
I'm seeing my mother on Sunday
are also virtually indistinguishable.
There are times, however, when the forms are not interchangeable or when ambiguity needs to be avoided.
- Semantic disqualification
With some verbs, arrangement is semantically possible. For example, we can have:
I'm turning up at my mother's party on Sunday
and
I am going to turn up at my mother's party on Sunday
with little difference, if any, in meaning.
But, if the meaning of the verb specifically excludes any possibility of an agreed arrangement then the progressive form is not possible so we can have:
I am going to surprise my mother by turning up at her party on Sunday
but not:
*I am surprising my mother by turning up at her party on Sunday
because, semantically, you cannot arrange to be surprised, astonished, excited, flabbergasted, bewildered etc. All these sorts of verbs are disqualified from appearing with the be + -ing form, therefore. - Avoiding ambiguity
The progressive form, in order to avoid ambiguity, usually needs to be accompanied by a time adverbial unless the context makes the future nature of the current plan clear. So, for example, we can have:
I'm going to drive to London
without context and the future sense is still clear.
However,
I'm driving to London
without any context is ambiguous and could mean:
I'm driving to London as we speak
I'm planning / have arranged to drive to London
or even
It is my current, temporary habit to drive to London (rather than use an alternative form of transport)
If the context does not clarify the situation as in, e.g.:
A: Can you come in early tomorrow?
B: Sorry. I'm taking the kids to school
we need to insert a time adverbial to disambiguate what we are saying so, e.g.:
I'm driving to London in the morning
or
I'm driving to London soon
are not ambiguous even without context because of the prepositional phrase adverbial or the adverb respectively. - Stative vs. Dynamic verb uses
The going to formulation can be used with verbs used statively so we allow, e.g.:
He's going to be angry when he gets the news
She's going to look wonderful at tonight's party
They are going to seem out of place in that company
we do not allow the progressive forms:
*He is being angry when he gets the news
*She's looking wonderful at tonight's party
*They are seeming out of place in that company
if the reference is to the future.
Both forms can be used with verbs used dynamically, only going to is used statively. - Inanimate subjects
We do not ascribe the ability to plan or form arrangements to inanimate objects so we allow, e.g.:
Look out! The ladder's going to slip in a minute
but not:
Look out! *The ladder's slipping in a minute.
This distinction is most noticeable when we are talking about the weather. Because it is inanimate, the weather is spoken about as:
It's going to rain tomorrow
but not as
It's raining tomorrow. - Present evidence
Only going to can be used to refer to present evidence leading to a future event. So we allow:
It's making her angry. She's going to lose her temper soon
but not
It's making her angry. She's losing her temper soon
Again, the present evidence rule applies when talking about inanimate objects such as the weather when present evidence is important so we get, for example:
Look at the clouds. It's going to rain soon
not
Look at the clouds. *It's raining soon. - Past experience
Prospective events based on past experience are also only realised through going to. For example, we allow:
When your father hears, he's going to laugh
but not
*When your father hears, he's laughing
even though the future reference is clear.
Again, past experience of weather conditions often makes the form suitable for that, too. For example:
It's going to snow a lot in Canada in January
not
*It is snowing a lot in Canada in January. - Conditional and contingent clauses
This is another sematic (or pragmatic) issue. For example, we allow:
If the trains aren't running, I'm going to drive
and it is a conditional expressing the fact that the speaker does not yet know if the trains will be running. However,
If the trains aren't running, I'm driving
does not have the same sense because it implies that the speaker already knows the trains are not running so has formed a plan or arrangement to drive. It could be realised as
As the trains aren't running, I'm driving. - Modal auxiliary verbs
Because most modal auxiliary verbs are defective in English and do not exhibit the full range of forms that lexical verbs do, there are severe limitations on the ways they can be used with either the going to or the be + -ing structure.- Deontic modality refers to duty or
obligation and we allow, e.g.:
I am going to have to talk to her
and
I am having to work long hours
but the second of these refers to present rather than future obligation and
?I am having to attend a meeting tomorrow
is at best questionable.
Other expressions of this form of modality which are rendered in the present with modal auxiliary verbs such as should and ought to.
There are no equivalent forms using either of these structures so, e.g.:
*He is going to ought to tell her
*The are shoulding do it
are not available.
Other languages allow future forms of equivalent modal auxiliary verbs and learners may be surprised to find that English does not. In fact, these deontic modal auxiliary verbs are used interchangeably in English to refer to present and future obligation as in, e.g.:
I should smoke less
I should talk to him
I ought to be better at this
I ought to tell her
etc. - Epistemic modality refers to
possibility and likelihood and are again not expressed with
these two structures so, e.g.:
*He is going to ought to be there by now
or
*She is shoulding be there soon
are not possible.
Again, both these future meanings are expressed using the same form for present and future time as in, e.g.:
She should be here before six tomorrow
They ought to arrive soon
It ought to work
It should be possible now
etc. - Alethic modality refers to the general
truth of a proposition and is usually timeless so present
forms are used and we cannot have, e.g.:
*A square is going to have to have four sides
or
*A square is having to have four sides. - Dynamic modality refers to the
individual's capabilities, as in, e.g.
I can see the point
etc.
The going to formulation is available for some forms of dynamic modality to refer to a present ability realised in the future so we allow, e.g.:
He is going to be able to help later
but we do not allow, e.g.:
*He is being able to help later
so the be + -ing form is not available to refer to current ability realised in the future.
- Deontic modality refers to duty or
obligation and we allow, e.g.:
- Arrangements
This is a marginal difference and more a tendency than a rule. By their nature, arrangements are made between people but intentions can be formed individually and only later communicated to others. Most English speakers will prefer, therefore:
All of us are meeting at the restaurant in the square tomorrow
to
All of us are going to meet at the restaurant in the square tomorrow
although both are possible with little effect on meaning.
However, in an exchange such as:
A: Are you writing to the boss about this?
B: No. I'm going to talk to her face to face.
then the second speaker has only now communicated a pre-formed intention. If the second speaker had said:
B: No. I'm meeting her face to face.
then the meaning is that the speaker and the boss have reached an agreement to meet.
Prospective aspect triggered by past events |
It is possible that the event or state which triggers the
future may even be in the past, omitting any reference to the
present altogether as in, e.g.:
We talked it over and we're going to emigrate.
We had a long chat and are moving in together.
which are both examples of a perfective past simple resulting
in a current prospective event.
The prospective present can also be combined with the perfect
as in, e.g.:
It has been agreed that I am driving / going to drive.
In the last case, we have a perfective action (completed) couched
in perfect form and followed by a prospective aspect in a present
tense (and either form is acceptable).
Take a short test to see if you can match aspect to meaning.