Deontic and alethic modality: expressing degrees of requirement
don't turn left, turn right |
Deontic modality refers to degrees of obligation (from the Greek déon, meaning roughly that which is done).
Alethic modality refers to given truths (from the Greek alēthia,
meaning truth).
They are treated together here because there is a considerable
overlap between that which is a given truth (a force of
circumstance) and that which one person chooses to oblige another to
do.
You may find deontic modality referred to as event
modality because it expresses the speaker / writer's view
of the desirability of an event being the case. We don't use
that term in this guide but it is an alternative.
You may also encounter alethic modality described as
circumstantial modality because it refers to
circumstances outside the control of and without relation to the
speakers involved in any kind of speech event. Alethic
modality would, philosophically speaking, exist even if there were
no beings capable of expressing it.
In the example above, we have used a simple imperative
verb form ((don't) turn) to express high degree of
obligation but we can also use other ways to express lower levels of
requirement or obligation, using for example, should or
ought (to).
Here are some examples. Your task, should you
choose to accept it, is to divide them into four categories
concerning how the ideas are realised in the structures of the
language (there are
two examples of each).
Click here when you have an answer.
- You must not turn left.
- Turning left is forbidden
- She obediently turned right
- They forbid you to turn left
- Turning right is obligatory
- She turned left illegally
- The sign tells you to turn right
- You have to turn right
- Modal auxiliary verbs
- You must not turn left
and You
have to turn right
Both of these use modal auxiliary verbs, and both express very high levels of obligation.
Both these verbs can be used to express lower levels of obligation because this area is one in which the roles of participants have a crucial influence.
Between equals, the verbs often signify advice rather than absolute obligation. E.g.:
You must see the film. It's terrific!
You have to come to the party. It'll be great. - Attributive clauses and adjectives
- Turning left is forbidden
and
Turning right is obligatory
Here, we have the attribute linked to the subject by the same copular verb, be.
In this category, we can also include the use of the passive as in, for example:
You are not permitted to turn left
and
You are required to turn right
because the structure is parallel and it is, in fact, not always straightforward to tell when the verb form is being used as a passive participle and when it is an adjective. It rarely matters for teaching purposes but one test is to make the structure active. - Modal adjuncts and disjuncts
- She obediently turned
right
She turned left illegally
These are quite rare ways to express a sense of obligation but they do occur.
Disjuncts such as:
Wisely, she turned right
also occur. - Verbal processes
- They forbid you to turn left
and The sign tells you to turn right
Both these verbs refer what is arguably a projecting process, bringing the inner world of they and the sign into the open. Whether road signs have an inner world is arguable, too, of course, but the authorities who caused this one to be erected certainly do. In these examples, the active is formed with the impersonal they (which is often the preferred pronoun for amorphous authority) but that need not be the case if the obliging authority is an individual or collective. E.g.:
The government have banned smoking in public spaces
The local authority has forbidden drinking alcohol in the park
Whose rules? |
Because deontic modality is to do with rules, it is tempting to
refer only to obligation when discussing the forms that can be used
to realise the function of allowing or forbidding.
However, rules are of different sorts and are often realised in
different ways through the language. Here are some sorts of
rules that apply to deontic modality.
- The law
- External obligations to do something or not to do something
are often rendered in stern terms, allowing little flexibility.
There is a built in threat that a failure to obey will result in unpleasant consequences. As a result, the modality is expressed through imperatives (often using no plus a noun phrase or gerund) and strong modal auxiliary verbs such as must, may, shall etc. For example:
No parking at any time
Passengers must not cross the line here
The tenant shall leave the premises in a fit state
No alcohol may be served after 11 pm
Give way to oncoming traffic
and so on. - Ethics
- Rules based on ethical systems and religions are not
enforceable in the same way as the law of a country but are
equally stern (often even sterner because the unpleasant
consequences last longer; for eternity in some views).
Rules derived from ethical systems are also, therefore, often
couched in similar terms to laws enshrined in constitutions.
For example:
Thou shalt not kill
Say your prayers three times a day
Love your neighbour
Alcohol is unlawful
etc. - Personal codes of conduct
- These are often derived from ethical systems (and there is
some overlap) but are also often not dependent on external views
so are less obviously obligations. Nevertheless, they lead
to expressions of deontic modality such as:
I cannot tell a lie
I swear to tell the truth
You should be kind to animals
Eating meat is wrong
and so on.
Personal codes of conduct often lead to admonitions to others, imperatives, softened or not, in an effort to get others to conform to the same code so we get:
Take your litter home
Turn off unwanted lights
Please consider our neighbours and leave quietly after 10 o'clock
etc.
Organisations rather than people also have codes of conduct which, while being non-obligatory and probably unenforceable except in unusual circumstances, carry a sense of obligation and, sometimes, the threat of sanctions. For example:
This space to be kept tidy
Our customers pay your wages: treat them with respect
etc. - Personal commitments
- These are allied to personal codes of conduct but instead of
enforcing an obligation on others (or everyone), the terms used
commit only the speaker or writer to the obligation. It is
a self-imposed obligation and sometimes called, therefore,
commissive modality. Examples are:
I'll pay you back tomorrow
I'll get that done for you
I'll come and help
I promise to be faithful
etc.
Organisations, too, indulge in commissive modality when they state, for example:
We will reply to your request within six working days
See below for more on this form of modality. - Requests
- These are often the result of a personal code of conduct
influencing a request (as in the last example above) but they
are also polite attempts to get others to do something and fall
within the purview of deontic modality. Examples include:
Please queue here
Please park tidily
and such requests are often couched in terms that make them seem like laws when they are in fact unenforceable such as:
Private property
No parking
Please close the gate
etc. - Advice
- While not placing an obligation on another, advice, too, is
a form of deontic modality because it concerns persuasion and
that is a form of obligation. Examples include:
You should see a dentist about that tooth
Why don't you write her a letter?
How about looking for another job?
and so on.
Overlapping categories |
Obligation vs. requirement
We can take these categories one by one to do a bit of analysis but first we need to see where the categories of obligation (deontic modality) and requirement (alethic modality) overlap. For example:
- One must study hard to succeed in the examination
- Success in the examination requires / needs hard study
- Success in the examination is only achievable by hard study
all express more or less the same idea using three of the different
structures as above, but do not carry the sense of a person
obliging another to do something. They express what the
speaker / writer sees as universal truths rather than advice or
admonition. This is a form of alethic modality.
An alternative analysis is to call these forms of modality
teleological because they refer to the end or aim of the person
concerned.
Alethic modality is more frequently used to refer to the physical
properties of the world around us. For example:
- You have / need to get the temperature up to 327.5°C to make lead melt
- You can only / must combine hydrogen and oxygen in a ratio of 2:1 to form water
- Occasionally, a leap second must be applied to Coordinated Universal Time (UTC) to keep it in line with mean solar time
The following examples lead to the same conclusion as the first set above regarding examination success but carry the sense of obligation by an external authority rather than expressing a universal truth:
- You must study hard to succeed in the examination
- I require you to study hard to succeed in the examination
- Your success in the examination will be achieved by your hard study
The categories overlap because one strong way of expressing obligation is to dress up what you say as if it were a universal truth rather than strong advice or person-to-person obligation. See the comments on need below for more on dressing deontic in alethic and epistemic clothes.
Whose obligation?
In the menagerie of terminology concerning modality, a distinction may also be drawn between different types of modality expressing requirement or obligation (or its lack):
- Deontic modality
properly expresses that which is necessary, obligatory or possible given a set of legal or moral principles. For example:
You must not drive over 70 miles per hour in Britain
You can't park here overnight
People should respect their elders - Boulemic modality
expresses that which is necessary given a person's wants and desires. For example:
I must go now
You must go to bed
I have to make a note or I'll forget it
In the first and third examples, the obligation rests on the speaker. In the second, the obligation is transferred to the hearer but the desire for compliance still comes from the speaker. - Teleological modality
expresses that which is necessary given a person's aims or desires. For example:
She'll have to study hard if she wants to pass the examination
If we want the meeting to start on time, we must get the opening speeches over quickly
External or internal?
In English language teaching, some make much of the concepts of
intrinsic or extrinsic obligation and aver, for example, that:
I have to eat more healthily
vs.
I must eat more healthily
represent different kinds of obligation, the first externally
imposed (by, e.g., a doctor or dietician) and the second internally
imposed by the speaker's wishes.
This is not really sustainable for two reasons:
- There is little evidence for this and native speakers use
the forms in free variation in most circumstances. Evidence
exists that the use of have to is increasing at the expense of must,
at least in spoken BrE. If this is true, the
extrinsic-intrinsic distinction between the forms cannot be
sustained.
Most native speakers will, for example, see very little if any difference at all in meaning between:
I must get an early night
and
I have to get an early night - The distinction is
hard to sustain. For example:
I must see the dentist about this tooth
vs.
I have to see the dentist about this tooth
Aside from the fact that most people would not see much difference in meaning, is toothache an external or internal condition?
You must learn the language if I want to live here
vs.
You have to learn the language if I want to live here
are arguably both forms of teleological modality and indistinguishable in meaning.
And so on.
Levels of obligation with modal auxiliary verbs |
The issue here is the strength of the modal auxiliary verbs. Some coursebooks and many teachers are tempted to invent some kind of cline between 0% and 100% obligation with a total lack of obligation at one end and an absolute command at the other. There are problems with this approach:
- It is almost impossible to get two native speakers to agree exactly where on the cline each verb should go.
- The verbs vary in deontic strength from mild advice to
absolute requirement depending on:
- the roles taken or assumed by speakers
- power relationships between people
- the topic: laws, physical or otherwise are often cases of alethic modality but opinions are the realm of deontic modality
The same modal auxiliary verb, then, can imply anything from mild advice to absolute command depending on who is using the language to whom to talk about what. The examples in the table below have to be interpreted in that light. The approach taken there is that the speaker / writer has some kind of authority to express obligation to another and it is not an exchange between equals.
There is some validity in having a cline such as:
but it has to remain mobile so that you can move things depending
on the variables concerned with stress and intonation as well as the
role relationships between speaker and hearer.
From a police officer:
You should get the brakes repaired
is an obligation but from a friend, it may simply be advice with no
possibility of an imposed obligation.
This is not the place for a detailed look at modal auxiliary verbs. That sort of guide appears elsewhere. Go to the general map of modality, linked below, to navigate to where you need to go.
Identifying three general levels of obligation – high, mid and low – can be a more helpful approach.
Now pause for a moment and consider which modal auxiliary verbs are used in each case. There are six choices:
- absolute obligation to do something
- absolute obligation not to do something
- advice to do something
- advice not to do something
- no obligation to do something
- no obligation not to do something
Click here when you have a list.
Commissive modality |
A sub-category of deontic modality is one in which the speaker
commits to a self-imposed obligation. In BrE, this is often
realised through the use of shall in expressions such as:
You shall have the money by Thursday
although in spoken language the contracted form ('ll)
disguises the use of shall and many believe it is a use of
will. The modal auxiliary verb will is often
used in this way but expresses volition or willingness rather than a commitment
as in
I will give you money on Thursday, if you like
which is dynamic modality rather than commissive or deontic modality
(and not, except incidentally, the use of the auxiliary verb to refer to
a future action. In fact, it is the verb functioning as a
primary auxiliary verb to make the aspect prospective).
There are other ways to realise the sense, e.g.:
I commit to getting the money to you by Thursday
I have made a commitment to get the money to you by Thursday
The money will be with you by Thursday – promise
Directive and Imperative modality |
These are two parallel sub-categories of deontic modality which refer to
the speaker / writer's view of how strong an obligation placed on
someone is.
This category can itself be further analysed and, for teaching
purposes, each type can be the topic of a lesson or mini-lesson.
Here is what is meant:
- Signalling a request for an instruction (sometimes called
deliberative modality):
Shall I clean the car?
Would you like me to post those?
etc. - Signalling an order or permission (imperative modality):
Come through
Enter!
Pass me that!
Work hard when you get to university
etc.
The sense can be immediate or delayed. - Signalling an obligation on a third person (sometimes called
a jussive mood):
Mary should be doing that
That's John's task
etc.
In some languages, such as German, a subjunctive form of the verb with the third person pronoun is used to express this. - Signalling the speaker / writer's view of the necessity of a
duty being fulfilled:
You must do as your mother says
She has to be on time
etc. - Signalling that something is obligatory to achieve an aim
(sometimes called teleological modality):
If you want to pass the examination, you must work hard - Signalling that something is an obligation given my wants
and desires (sometimes called boulemic modality):
I must get something to eat; I'm starving - Signalling that something is more of a request than an
order:
Do you think you can get this done by Monday?
Please follow me
etc.
How the modality will be interpreted depends on the authority perceived. For example:
Follow me
may be a simple request between equals, but, if it is written in lights on the rear of a police car is an absolute imperative. - Signalling a prohibition
Do not disturb
You can't park here
That is forbidden
etc.
Sources of potential confusion with modal auxiliary verbs |
- These auxiliaries are also used to express degrees of truth
of a proposition as the speaker / writer understands it
(epistemic modality) and, if the use is not made clear by very
explicit contexts which include the speaker / writer's
intentions, there is a danger of confusing learners. For
example:
- She must / should / ought to be in London by 6 o'clock (probably expressing deductive or evidential epistemic modality: the speaker's understanding of the truth of the proposition based on the available evidence)
- She must / should / ought to be in London at 6 o'clock (probably expressing deontic modality: the speaker's obligation on her or comment on an external obligation)
- She may leave early
This auxiliary expresses both deontic modality so it could mean:
She is allowed to leave early
and epistemic modality so it could mean:
It is possible (but unlikely) that she will leave early.
Only context can disambiguate the issue. - Might she come?
Again, might can be used in both senses:
deontic:
Is she allowed to come?
epistemic:
Is it likely that she will come?
For this reason, speakers will often select a different formulation and ask:
Do you think she will come?
(epistemic) or
Can she come?
(deontic) to show which kind of meaning is to be understood.
-
In the past, there are three issues:
- although the levels of obligation are unchanged, the form of
e.g.,
They shouldn't have said that
looks like a present perfect and learners may be tempted consider it conceptually like that. It is, however, in sense, akin to a past simple because the event referred to is finished in the past. For more, see the guide to modality and aspect, linked below. - the past of should (not), ought (not) to and
need not imply
that an obligation in the past was not fulfilled:
She shouldn't have gone (but did so the obligation was not fulfilled)
We should have said sorry (but didn't so the obligation was not fulfilled)
I ought to have been there (but wasn't so the obligation was not fulfilled)
I oughtn't to have said that (but did so the obligation was not fulfilled)
I needn't have gone alone (but did so the obligation was not fulfilled) - the past of have to, however, implies that the
obligation was
fulfilled
I had to see the doctor yesterday (and did so the obligation was fulfilled)
I didn't have to see the doctor (so didn't so the lack of obligation was fulfilled)
- although the levels of obligation are unchanged, the form of
e.g.,
Personal and impersonal expressions of obligation: verbs and attributive clauses |
|
I advise you against that |
These examples are of common ways in which personal expression of obligation can be achieved. The strength of the obligation conveyed is a semantic issue to do with the meaning of the verbs:
- I forbade them to do it
- I permitted them to go
- The teacher expected them to come on time
- She advised him to wait
Using a passive construction removes the personal effect of the verbs:
- They were forbidden to do it
- They were permitted to go
- They were expected to come on time
- He was advised to wait
Using attributive clauses with the dummy it-structure further reduces the level of the personal although whether these should all be analysed as a form of passive with a verbal structure or a use of participle adjectives is disputable:
- It was compulsory to stay
- It was expected that they came on time
One minor way is through the use of a marginal modal (or semi-auxiliary):
- We were supposed to stay
Face saving and face threatening: dressing deontic modality in epistemic clothes |
Impersonal statements of deontic modality are often used as a way
to avoid what is known as a face-threatening act (Goffman, 1967).
A direct order such as:
Take these to the bank now
can be seen as threatening the face of the hearer because it places
him or her in a subordinate, more humble position socially. To
avoid that, many speakers in authority roles may prefer to say:
The bank expects these soon
and leave it to the hearer to make the connection between that and
an imperative (which it remains).
Deontic modality, expressed through verbs like must, have to,
ought to and should may be seen as a face threatening
and making the hearer subservient.
For this reason, speakers will often dress up the imposition by
selecting a different formulation. A common one is the use of
the semi-modal need which implies less of a personal
imposition and more of a fact without which something cannot occur.
In this sense, it can be seen as a form of alethic or epistemic
modality, because it refers to the truth of a proposition. The
communicative effect, however, is often deontic.
There are times when need, must and have to may
be used interchangeably but there are some important differences in
nuance.
For example:
You must buy a ticket
You have to buy a ticket
You need to buy a ticket
may be considered synonymous and, in many cases, they are.
All of these are examples of deontic modality. So, for
example,
You have to fill in a form
or
You must fill in a form
refers to the hearer’s duty and the obligation placed on him/her by
the speaker or by an external authority.
However, in
You need to fill in a form
The semi-modal need implies that it is a general rather
than personal requirement, to do with the logical necessity of
something being true (epistemically).
This form is often used, for example, in the passive as:
To be processed, the form needs to be submitted before
the end of the month
which states a conditional necessity rather than a personal
obligation.
This may also be termed teleological modality in that it represents
the need for a condition to be fulfilled before an aim is reached.
The verb need often implies some undesired consequence in the way that
must and have to do not. For example,
choosing the formulation
You need to be at the station by 6 (or you'll
miss the train)
expresses the preference for avoiding the unwelcome logical
consequence while
You must be at the station by 6
expresses more direct obligation.
Face-saving for the hearer is often the motivation for selecting
need over the more direct model verbs of obligation.
In, for example:
Everyone needs to be in the office by 8 o'clock
no personal obligation is implied because this is simply company
policy and not my imposition on you or anyone else. It is a
statement of fact, sounds more polite and distances the speaker from
any sense of assumed authority.
Compare, too, the use of need in, for example:
The bank needs to have these figures tomorrow
with
You have to / must give the bank the figures tomorrow
because the first saves the face of the hearer by not imposing
authority on him/her.
Finally, we can ignore (if we wish) any statement using must
or have to because we are independent operators. So,
for example:
You have to come at 6 o’clock
is an obligation I can ignore if I choose and that might upset
someone else, but
You need to come at 6 o’clock
is probably not because it implies that I will miss something
important if I don’t, not that someone else will be upset.
Related guides: | |
non-modal-verb modality | covers some of the above and extends it to include epistemic and other forms of modality |
modality and aspect | for the guide to how aspect is realised with modal auxiliary verbs |
epistemic modality | which follows a similar format to this one |
dynamic modality | which follows a similar format to this one |
multiple modalities | for a guide which considers how different types of modality may be combined in single utterances |
mood | for a guide which considers the three main moods signalled by verb changes in English and some moods in other languages |
ambiguity | for a guide which considers the polysemous nature of many modal auxiliary verbs and the ambiguity which can arise |
the modality map | for more choices |
References:
Goffman, E, 1967, Interaction Ritual: Essays on Face-to-Face
Behavior, New York: Doubleday
Palmer, FR, 2001, Mood and Modality, 2nd edition,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press