Types of modality
There is a simpler and much abbreviated essential guide to modality in the pre-service, initial plus section of this site and one to central modal auxiliary verbs. Both those links will open in new tabs.
What follows is an analysis which can be used when planning to teach modal auxiliary verbs, modal adjectives, adverbs and nouns in English. It is based on some fundamental concepts in logic and the theory is that the categories of modality mirror the categories of human thought, making concepts clearer and more teachable.
Propositions and Modality distinguished |
At the outset, we need to distinguish between propositions and modality because that will help us to define what we are talking about.
If, for example, I say:
The door is red
I am not implying any sense of whether it should be red, must
be red, can't be black or whatever. I am simply stating a
proposition and the hearers will make of it what they will.
If, however, I say:
You need to use the red door
I am stating something very different. In effect, I am saying
that there is some kind of obligation or duty on the hearer to use
one door rather than another. In other words, I am stating my
perception of the situation rather than stating a fact.
This guide is concerned with how English speakers express their
feelings about events and states.
This is an important area because it is impossible to speak any
language properly without knowing how to encode your feelings about
events and states. Confining yourself to statements about the
world only is akin to trying to write a novel without using the
letter 'e' and is communicatively crippling.
Unfortunately, it's also a complex area and the complications are
often underestimated.
There is, to muddy the water slightly, a distinction sometimes made between event modality and propositional modality. Luckily, the two types of modality can be simply explained:
- Event modality refers to the perceived benefit of an event
occurring. For example:
This work must be completed by August
It is important that the staff are kept informed
which both refer to how the speaker / writer perceives a benefit from an event. - Propositional modality refers to the speaker / writer's view of
likelihood of a proposition being true. For example:
That's obviously his sister
She should be in Paris by now
which both refer to how likely the speaker perceives a proposition is true.
In the analysis used on this site, event modality concerns deontic modality and propositional modality concerns epistemic modality. For an explanation of those two terms, read on.
Modality lies in the realms of interpersonal meanings and expresses
how the speaker / writer feels about a state or event: whether it
is true, necessary, inevitable, possible, desirable and so on.
Modality is a semantic phenomenon rather than a
syntactical one because it is concerned with meaning and meaning can
be realised through a wide range of structures.
All of the
following are, therefore, expressions of modality of one kind or
another:
|
|
You will see that only six of those examples contain a modal auxiliary verb (need, must, can (twice), should, will). In what follows, many examples of modal auxiliary verbs are used to exemplify the concepts but you should not assume that such verbs are the only way of expressing modality. The other examples above contain modal adjectives (necessary, willing, unable), modal nouns (conclusion, obligation), modal adverbs (probably, definitely), and lexical or main verbs used to express modality (freeze, expect, manage, pass, mean).
Views of modality |
A traditional view |
Traditionally, modality is taught in two main ways:
- By taking modal auxiliary verbs or other expressions of
modality and seeing what kinds of meaning they carry. This
is a common analysis (used elsewhere on this site in the
consideration of modal auxiliary verbs) taking each verb in turn
and itemising and explaining what functions they can perform.
For example, with the modal auxiliary verb might and
other ways to express the meanings it can realise we get:
Function Example present possibility Careful. There might be a snake in the hall.
I think it's possible there is a snake in the hallfuture possibility It might rain tomorrow.
The weather forecast is for rain tomorrow.past possibility He might have telephoned while I was out.
It's possible he telephoned while I was out.suggestion You might try taking an aspirin.
Perhaps an aspirin helps.permission Might I talk to you?
Do you have a little time to talk to me?complaint You might have warned me!
It is regrettable that you didn't warn me. - By looking at some ways of describing modality and see how
we can realise the meanings in English. This means looking
at concepts such as:
Ability:
I can go
I am able to go
Permission:
You may go
I allow you to go
Advice:
You should go
Going is advisable
Obligation:
They must go
They are required to go
Possibility:
They might go
Perhaps going is what they will do
However, both these approaches have drawbacks.
- Approach 1.
- can easily overwhelm learners because a single verb (might in this case) can express six different and unconnected meanings and other modal auxiliary verbs suffer from the same polysemous state so verbs like can and should are used in English to represent many meanings (ability, permission, deduction etc.) and there is no one-to-one relationship between the verb and its meaning.
- Approach 2.
- is unfortunately too loose because the categories do not
lead to any sensible decisions about what they mean and they
overlap.
For example, does:
Off you go!
express permission or obligation?
Does:
I can do that for you
express ability or possibility?
Does:
He should be there
represent a deduction about a possibility or some advice?
Does:
You must try some of this chocolate cake
mean I am giving advice or obliging you to do something?
and so on.
A different view |
The traditional views have the advantage of being familiar and using terms readily understood by everyone but, for teaching purposes, they are flawed ways to do the analysis. Speakers of the language do not proceed from a consideration of the various functions of the verb, adjective, noun or adverb and then make meaning using it. What they do is to conceive a meaning and then select a modal expression which suits their purposes.
We need a better representation of modality which does two things:
- Avoids the overlapping, loosely defined categories
- Represents types of modality which bear a greater resemblance to how people think
With this in mind, we can try an alternative way to represent the diversity of modal auxiliary verbs and other modal expressions using adverbs, nouns, lexical verbs and adjectives in English.
For example, I may have in mind the fact that I do not believe
Mary when she says:
Hey, I saw a unicorn on my way back from the pub last night!
For my purposes, I might select any number of expressions of
modality depending on my degree of certainty, formality, the setting,
how well I know Mary, whether I owe her obedience and
so on.
I may consider, for example:
It's an impossibility that you saw a unicorn
You can't have seen a unicorn
If you say so, it must be true
It is impossible that you saw a unicorn
I suppose you might have seen a unicorn, but I doubt it
You couldn't have seen a unicorn; they don't come round here
and so on.
These examples are forms of epistemic modality (i.e., to do with the speaker's view of the truth of a proposition) although the verbs and expressions themselves can be used to express other types of modality. They all express a degree of certainty about the central proposition.
4 shades of modality |
- epistemic modality
- Epistemology is the study of theories of knowledge and the
word epistemic means relating to knowledge.
This kind of modality is to do with the speaker's perception of the truth or otherwise of a proposition. In the loose traditional terms, it's to do with (im)possibility, (un)likelihood, (un)certainty etc.
So, for example, on hearing a knock at the door, the use of will in:
That will be the postman
signals the speaker's certainty about the proposition.
Equally:
That can't be the postman
signals the speaker's certainty of untruth and the use of might in:
That might be the postman
signals the speaker's uncertainty.
Modal auxiliary verbs of deduction fall into this category (should, must, can, ought and more), as do expressions such as:
I think that's the postman
I don't believe that's the postman
Do you reckon that's the postman?
My feeling is that that's the postman
It's impossible that it's the postman
I suppose it's the postman
and so on. - deontic modality
- Deontology is the study of duty and deontic means
relating to obligation and duty (or its lack). In
the loose traditional terms, it's to do with obligation, lack of
obligation, advice, duty, prohibition, necessity etc.
For example, the use of ought to in:
You ought to write to your mother
expresses the speaker's perception that it is the hearer's duty to write and the use of must in:
You must not write like that
expresses the speaker's view that the hearer is obliged not to write in that way.
The use of may in:
You may go
expresses the speaker's view that there is no longer a duty or obligation to stay.
Modal auxiliary verbs expressing any sense of obligation or its lack (should, must, can, may, might, ought and more), prohibition and advice fall into this category as do expressions such as:
Your mother will be expecting a letter from you
It's your duty to write
Writing like that is unwise
I'm telling you not to write like that
Go if you like
It's not necessary to stay
and so on. - dynamic modality
- The term dynamic needs no explanation but here it
refers to the fact that the modality is centred on the subject
and encompasses ability and willingness.
In the loose traditional term, it's to do with ability but the
willingness aspect is often ignored or put into considerations
of talking about the future (where it does not belong and has
served to confuse and bewilder generations of learners and,
alas, some teachers).
For example, the use of could in:
I could swim well as a child
refers to the subject's own ability and not to externally imposed obligations or duties or any sense of likelihood or impossibility and the use of can in:
Can you understand this?
refers to the hearer's ability alone and:
I'll get it for you
refers to the speaker's willingness to do something (volition). It is not, incidentally, a future tense form and does not necessarily refer to the future at all; it is an expression of current willingness to do something. The modal auxiliary verbs expressing ability or willingness (will, would and can mostly) fall into this category as do expressions such as:
I had the ability to swim well as a child
I was able to swim well as a child
Are you going to help me with this?
I need some help with this
I'm willing to get it for you
Let me get it
and so on.
Dynamic modality is sometimes called personal modality because it applies, in most cases, to people's abilities and willingness. - alethic modality
- This term derives from the Greek word for truth
[αλήθεια, aleethia] and refers to logical necessity (rather than
deduction which concerns epistemic modality). For example, the use of must in:
A square must have four sides
refers not to the speaker's perception and not to any form of obligation, ability or deduction but to the fact that one of the necessary conditions of being a square is to have four sides and the use of can't in:
Parallel lines can't meet
equally represents the truth of a proposition, failing which the lines cannot be parallel. A few modal auxiliary verbs (must, can't, will, mustn't and need mostly) fall into this category as does the present simple tense form of the verb and other expressions such as:
A defining characteristic of squares is that they have four equal sides
Lines which are parallel never meet
In a sense, this form of modality is the odd one out because it does not rely on the speaker's view of an event or state. Alethic modality is concerned with what is universally true in all cases independent of the setting.
Subtler shades |
This area of study is infested with a menagerie of terminology,
some of which is concerned with quite subtle levels of analysis.
So, if you come across alternative expressions, here's a very short
guide:
- Epistemic modality is often singled out as being views of
the truth based solely on the evidence available to the speaker
and separated in that way from alethic modality which is not
contingent on the speaker's setting but expresses truths in all
possible worlds. We make a distinction between the two
types here, too, but should bear in mind that they overlap
slightly so, for example:
This must be the answer
That can't be right
can express the speaker's certainty that it is correct or not or that the truth is an inevitable outcome of the laws of mathematics depending on the situation referred to.
Epistemic modality is sometimes further broken down, e.g., by Palmer, 2001, into:- judgemental or speculative modality: referring to the
speaker's judgement or understanding. For example:
I think that's too much
That might not be enough
etc. - deductive or evidential modality: referring to the
speaker's view as influenced by evidence. For example:
It might rain later
I think it's going to be a difficult job - assumptive modality: expressing the speaker's view of
the truth based on previous experience. For example:
She'll be at work at this time of the morning
Don't call now. They'll be having dinner.
- judgemental or speculative modality: referring to the
speaker's judgement or understanding. For example:
- Deontic modality is sometimes distinguished from or broken
down further as:
- boulemic modality: that which is necessary given a person's wants and
desires. For example:
I must go now and get something to eat
You must not stay if you have work to do
etc. - jussive modality: an obligation placed on a third
person. The jussive mood is also used in some languages
with a distinctive verb form to express wishes about the actions
of a third person. For example:
He really should try to be more patient with the children
Mary has to be the one to do it
etc. - commissive modality: an obligation placed on the speaker
by the speaker. For example:
I will pay tomorrow
I'll get it done; promise
I have to thank you
etc. - imperative or directive modality: an obligation placed
on the hearer. For example:
You should get some rest
This has to be done before we can go - teleological modality: that which is necessary to
achieve an aim as in, e.g.:
If you want to get into university you need to study hard
We must leave now or we'll miss the train
This form of modality is often expressed with conditional structures as above.
- boulemic modality: that which is necessary given a person's wants and
desires. For example:
- Dynamic modality is often referred to as ability or personal modality (because that is what is mostly concerns). That is not compatible with the view taken in these sections of the site because we also consider expressions of willingness as falling into this category.
- Alethic modality is sometimes referred to as circumstantial
modality because it derives from the circumstances of the
universe and expresses universal truths (which epistemic
modality does not). For example:
Paper will spontaneously ignite at 233° C
which is true wherever you are and not dependent on when or where you state it.
For obscure reasons, you may also see this type of modality described as root modality but not on this site.
For teaching purposes and for the analysis of language for
planning, these subtleties are probably unnecessary, although some languages
deal with the categories differently, using a variety of means,
often the subjunctive or other forms of verbs. However, if you
are interested in the philosophy of language, they have some
utility.
That said, for single lessons, it is often wise to take just one or
two sub-sections of the main types of epistemic and deontic modality
to keep the focus and help learners acquire the concepts. It
also makes some sense to handle volition and ability separately when
considering dynamic modality.
Modal (auxiliary) verbs |
On many training courses, attention is given to what are, rather loosely called modal verbs or, even more loosely, just modals. The most obvious problem is that there is little consistency in the literature (or in teachers rooms) concerning what should be analysed as what.
Elsewhere on this site, ten pure modal auxiliary verbs are
recognised:
can | could | may |
might | must | shall | should | will | would| ought to
and the expression had better
can be added to that list because it behaves much like a central
modal auxiliary verb.
In addition, there are some less pure verbs such as
be able | be
going |
have |
along with semi-modal auxiliary verbs including
need | used
| dare
Added to the mix are marginal modal auxiliary verbs such as
be supposed | tend |
care
and many more.
Other lexical or main verbs such as
let | prohibit | ban |
forbid | allow | follow | mean | involve
and so on also express modality of one kind or another (sometimes
more than one).
All these verbs are considered on this site and can be tracked down from the general index of modality linked in the list at the end.
An alternative analysis of modality |
The following is not meant to be exhaustive but, for most
English-language teaching purposes, it will suffice as a starting
point when planning to teach modality based on mental
processes rather than form or vague semantic categories.
The alternative modal expressions are suggestive only and include
modal adverbials, nouns and adjectives.
Epistemic modality |
|
That must be the teacher's desk |
Modal auxiliary verb | Example | Alternative modal expressions |
might | If there's too
little current, the pump might not work He might have telephoned while I was out Might she have left early? |
It's
possible the pump isn't working. Possibly, he's already gone out. I'm assuming the pump isn't broken. My assumption is that that's the postman. I'm sure that is what he said. It's obviously his brother. It's clear they are related. It seems likely that it's him. I doubt she is there. I expect that's the postman |
could | It could rain
tomorrow He couldn't have gone out this early Could he already be here? |
|
can | The pump can't
be broken. It's new It can get cold in the winter Can it be her? |
|
should | Ah, that
should be the postman now It shouldn't be late Should the train come soon? |
|
would | Well, he
would, wouldn't he? It's in his interests That would be his mother you saw Would that be the right number? |
|
must | That must be his brother. Aren't they alike? | |
may | Well it may be
his brother. I don't know She may not be the right person to ask |
|
will | That will be
the postman at the door That won't be the postman. It's too early Will that be your mother ringing? |
|
ought to | She ought to be there by now |
On the right, there are examples of positive, negative and interrogative forms. Where one or more is missing, the forms are not used:
- may in an interrogative always implies permission rather than likelihood
- ought in the negative and interrogative always implies advice or prohibition
- The negative and interrogative of must for epistemic modality is encoded with couldn't / can't
For more on how epistemic modality is expressed in English, see the guide to expressing (un)certainty and the fuller guide to epistemic modality, both linked from the list of related guides at the end.
Deontic modality |
|
They shall not pass |
Modal auxiliary verb | Example | Alternative modal expressions |
might | Might I ask a question? | Is
there a chance of asking a question? Do you have a moment? Seeing a doctor would be advisable. I forbid you to speak to me like that. Is he allowed to come, too? Do you have permission to be here? I don't imagine this work will take long. They are advised to get here early. If I were you, I'd see a dentist. It's her duty to write. Registration is compulsory. I advise you to leave soon. |
could | Could I just say something? | |
can | Can I see you
for a minute? You can go You can't sleep here |
|
should | You should not
speak to me like that Should I wait for you? You should see a doctor |
|
must | You must finish
the work before 6 You mustn't turn right here Must I get a ticket? |
|
need | This work
needn't take long They need to get here early Do you need to see me? |
|
may | May he come
with us, please? You may not use a dictionary You may start |
|
will | You will not
speak to me so rudely again You will stay until we have finished |
|
ought to | She ought to
write to her father Ought you to go soon? I oughtn't to be so impatient with her |
|
have (got) to | You have (got) to
register online Have I (got) to explain again? They don't have to come if they don't want to |
|
had better | Hadn't you
better leave soon? I had better go soon You had better not try that again |
|
shall | You shall not
speak to your father like that Officers shall be properly dressed at all times |
On the right, there are examples of positive, negative and interrogative forms. Where one or more is missing, the forms are not used:
- might in positive statements and negatives usually refers to likelihood
- could in a positive or negative form usually implies ability rather than permissibility
- will and shall in an interrogatives usually refer to futurity or willingness
In some of the above, of course, there is an implied reference to
possibility (i.e., epistemic modality). For example,
Do you have a moment?
can be interpreted as a question about a
current state but is more likely to mean
Do you give me
permission to interrupt your day?
and
I think registration is compulsory
can be interpreted simply as a
statement of opinion but is more likely to mean
You probably have to
register.
The verb need can also imply alethic modality as in,
e.g.:
Dogs need walks
which implies a simple truth rather than an obligation per
se.
The verb also has a non-modal use as a lexical or main verb meaning
require as is, e.g.:
We are going to need a bigger boat
For more on how deontic modality is expressed in English, see the guide to expressing obligation and the fuller guide to deontic and alethic modality, both linked from the list of related guides at the end.
Dynamic modality |
|
We can do this! |
Strictly speaking, dynamic modality is confined to expressions of ability or willingness. That will limit the number of modal auxiliary verbs quite severely to can, could, will, would and be able to for the most part (and the last of those is more sensibly analysed as a modal adjective).
Modal auxiliary verb | Example | Alternative modal expressions |
can | I can speak Spanish
well. Can you believe it! I can't manage alone |
She has
the ability to speak 4 languages. Is that believable? I haven't the strength to do it. I am happy to accept. Please help me. I volunteer to do that. Let me go; I know the way. Did you manage to find what you wanted? |
could | I couldn't
possible lift it She could read well at the age of 4 Could you give me some help? |
|
will | I'll get the door I won't interfere Will you do the washing up? |
|
would | I would love to
come I wouldn't give you the money, anyway Would you come with me, please? |
|
able to | Were you able
to find what you wanted? I wasn't able to see her She was able to get it all done |
For more on how dynamic modality is expressed in English, see the fuller guide linked from the list of related guides at the end.
Alethic modality |
|
The blue bit can't go here. |
Modal auxiliary verb | Example | Alternative modal expressions |
must | A quintet must contain 5 players. | Unless
it has five players, it's not a quintet. Having more or fewer than 8 players disqualifies it as an octet. It is necessary to have 4 sides in a square. |
can't | An octet can't have more or fewer than 8 players. | |
need | A square needs 4 sides. |
When expressing alethic modality, the verb must is
negated in standard English as can't or couldn't
(as it is for epistemic modality). In some dialect forms,
however, mustn't is used to express impossibility rather
than negative obligation. So we can encounter:
That mustn't be the right number
which for most speakers suggests deontic modality, instead of the
standard:
That can't be the right number
The verb can is not used in the positive for this meaning
as it implies epistemic, deontic or dynamic modality in that form.
The verb need is somewhat rarer in this sense but does
occur in, for example:
The temperature needs to be over 40°C for this
to work
It is not used in the negative in this sense.
It is also quite rare for alethic modality to be expressed in the
past because, obviously, it usually refers to timeless facts which
are independent of the speaker's existence.
It is occasionally encountered when a fact has been superseded and
is no longer true, for example:
At that time a battle had to be fought on foot.
in such cases, the normal rule of replacing must with
have to and can't with couldn't applies.
However, the verb need is not negated in the past when it
is used to express alethic modality, so, e.g.:
At that time armies needed to move solely on foot
cannot be negated as
At that time armies didn't need to move solely on foot
or
At that time armies needn't have moved solely
on foot
because that implies a lack of obligation rather than a negative
fact.
The guide to expressing degrees of likelihood, linked below, includes considerations of alethic modality and considers the overlap between it and epistemic modality.
Multiple modalities |
It is possible, in all languages, to combine modalities in single
utterances such as:
She should be able to do that
(combining epistemic and dynamic modalities)
They may have to see a doctor (combining epistemic and
deontic modalities)
Peter might be allowed to go home early (combining
epistemic and deontic modalities)
and so on.
The issue in English in particular is that the rules of the
language's syntax do not allow the co-occurrence of pure or central modal
auxiliary verbs so we cannot have, e.g.:
*She must can come with us
as we may in many other languages.
There are a number of workarounds for this problem in English which
are discussed in the guide to multiple modalities, linked below, and
many concern the use of semi- and marginal-modal verbs as well as
modal nouns, lexical or main verbs, adjectives and adverbs.
Entailment |
This is a term dealt with in more detail in the guide on this site to pragmatics, linked below, and it follows on from ideas of multiple modalities.
Entailment concerns the understanding of truth and therefore
falls into the realm of epistemic modality so, for example, if
someone proposes:
John saw a kangaroo while he was on holiday
in Australia
Then we know not only that the statement appears to be true but also
that:
- It is possible to see kangaroos in Australia (epistemic modality)
- John must have been in Australia (epistemic modality)
- John was certainly on holiday (epistemic modality)
- Kangaroos are visible (alethic modality)
- John must be able to see (epistemic and dynamic modality)
but not - John was certainly not in Australia
- There are no kangaroos in Australia
- John cannot see
- Kangaroos must be invisible
- John never has a holiday
The last five propositions are automatically disallowed by the proposition we began with and are not expressive of any form of modality but the first five are entailed in the comment.
In terms of modality, entailment is a useful concept because, for example:
- I can help with that
is probably an example of dynamic modality expressing willingness, but it also entails another form of dynamic modality expressing ability. It may, in fact, be an example of an expression of ability but it is unlikely to be said if that, too, did not entail an expression of willingness (otherwise, why say it?). One of the rules of speech identified by Grice is that we do not normally over inform and if this comment does not entail an expression either of willingness or ability, it would break that maxim. - You should write to your mother soon
is clearly an example of deontic modality, expressing the speaker's view that an action is advisable but it also entails dynamic modality because it would not be said if the speaker did not believe the hearer was able to write to her mother. - God could make a kangaroo with three tails but he
couldn't make a triangle with four sides
is clearly a comment concerning dynamic modality (positive and negative ability) but there is an entailed alethic modality embedded in the comment because we know that a triangle must have three and only three sides. - I'll buy some petrol so I can use the mower this
afternoon
is a statement of commissive deontic modality with an obligation put by the speaker on the speaker but there is also an entailment of epistemic modality concerning the speaker's view that the mower will not function unless petrol is supplied and there is a further sense of dynamic modality concerning the speaker's expression of ability.
Modality is not simple.
Miscellaneous notes |
- In some analyses, the modal auxiliary verb must is classified
as representing intrinsic or even (mistakenly) dynamic modality because it is
seen as personal to the speaker rather than an externally
imposed duty and have to appears under
extrinsic deontic modality because, the theory has it, it
expresses an externally imposed duty. However,
where it is not obvious which is intended, native speakers use
them in free variation.
It is also the case that it is difficult to separate the external from the internal so, for example:
I have a toothache and have to go to the dentist
can just as well be expressed as:
I have a toothache and must go to the dentist
because it is unclear whether a toothache represents an internal or external phenomenon. - The strength of both deontic and epistemic modality is often determined by intonation and stress rather than depending on the modal expression chosen by the speaker.
- In this analysis, logical deduction and logical necessity are distinguished (as epistemic and alethic modalities) but, for most teaching purposes, can be conflated.
- Teaching modal expressions using this kind of analysis
presumes that you start from the type of modality your learners
need to express and work on a limited range of ways to realise
the mental processes in English.
There is a guide on this site, linked below, to teaching modality.
Summary
Here's a summary with examples using pure (or central) modal
auxiliary verbs only. Semi-modal auxiliary verbs and marginal modal
auxiliary verbs can also express different types of modality. All four
types of modality can also be expressed without modal auxiliary
verbs at all.
For teaching purposes, the summary is useful because you can see at
a glance whether the lesson you planned mixes the same verb
expressing different forms of modality. That can confuse,
especially at lower levels.
Here's another summary which contains a few of the other
sub-categories you may encounter along with some examples as an aide
memoire.
For an explanation of them, go to the dedicated guides, linked
below.
And here is a final set of examples to show five ways in which the four types of modality are commonly achieved in English. It's not complete and there are more examples in the guides linked at the end. In particular, the guide to modality without modal auxiliary verbs has many more examples of other ways to realise modal ideas.
To check your understanding, try a multiple choice quiz on this area.
Related guides | |
the modality index | for links to all relevant sections |
essential guide to modality | a simpler guide in the initial training section |
modality map | a way to find your way around a complex area containing a clickable map |
central modal auxiliary verbs | a traditional view taking each modal in turn and identifying its function |
semi-modal auxiliary verbs | which also considers marginal modal auxiliary verbs such as seem, tend, be about to etc. |
modality without modal auxiliary verbs | which considers adverbials, verbs, adjectives and nouns used to express modality |
epistemic modality | modality for expressing the speaker's view of the truth or a proposition, i.e., likelihood |
expressing uncertainty | a functional approach to epistemic modality |
deontic modality | modality for expressing the speaker's view of obligation or its lack with some consideration of alethic modality with which it overlaps |
dynamic modality | modality for expressing ability and willingness |
multiple modalities | for the guide to how English manages to combine types of modality |
pragmatics | for more about entailment and much else |
complex tenses | which also considers complex tenses in relation to modal auxiliary verbs |
teaching modality | for some more ideas transferable to the analysis above |
modality and aspect | which considers modal auxiliary verbs with perfect and progressive forms and considers some of the types of modality discussed here |
test yourself | go here for a set of six linked tests on types and realisations of modality |
Reference:
Palmer, FR, 2001, Mood and Modality,
2nd ed., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
and some more.